Wittgenstein Posthumously Solves the Species Problem

On a longstanding problem in biology and how philosophy helps

by Massimo Pigliucci Philosophy Now edited by O Society April 12, 2019

Biologists and (some) philosophers seem to share an obsession: they apparently never tire of discussions about the nature of biological species. What exactly is a species?

If you happen to enroll in graduate studies in ecology, evolutionary biology, or philosophy of biology, the likelihood that you will have to sit through a semester-long seminar on the topic is high indeed. Moreover, you will probably leave that seminar with little more understanding of what species are than when you entered it.

And yet, the ‘species problem’ is certainly fundamental to biology, and hence to philosophy of science. It is not by chance that Darwin titled the most important book ever written in biology (and possibly in the whole of science), On the Origin of Species:

“Nor shall I here discuss the various definitions which have been given of the term ‘species.’ No one definition has as yet satisfied all naturalists; yet every naturalist knows vaguely what he means when he speaks of a species. Generally the term includes the unknown element of a distinct act of creation. The term ‘variety’ is almost equally difficult to define; but here community of descent is almost universally implied.

Hence, in determining whether a form should be ranked as a species or a variety, the opinion of naturalists having sound judgment and wide experience seems the only guide to follow. We must, however, in many cases, decide by a majority of naturalists, for few well-marked and well-known varieties can be named which have not been ranked as species by at least some competent judges.”

It isn’t that people don’t have a choice: a recent count lists a whopping 26 different concepts of species proposed in the literature! Part of the problem is that biologists (and some, but not all, philosophers) keep adopting an essentialist concept of species: there has to be one right way to think of the problem, and hence one unique solution, which we would surely find if only we had more data (say biologists) or thought a bit harder (say some philosophers).

The trouble with this view is perhaps clear if one considers the most popular such proposal: the so-called ‘biological’ species concept (what concept of species would not be biological, one wonders?) originally articulated by Theodozius Dobzhansky and Ernst Mayr in the 1930s and ’40s. The idea is that members of the same species are recognizable as such because they can actually or potentially interbreed with one another.

Even a superficial critical analysis of this concept cannot fail to notice ‘potential’ interbreeding opens up a Pandora’s box of conceptual problems. But one need not go that far in order to find trouble. By that definition, all bacteria, many plants, and a wide array of living forms simply cannot have species, because they don’t reproduce sexually (and therefore cannot ‘interbreed’, potentially or otherwise). This is a spectacular case of throwing out the baby with the bathwater.

Similar limitations apply to other definitions of species suggested over the years, and this has eventually led some philosophers and biologists (B.D. Mishler, M.J. Donoghue, P. Kitcher, and J. Dupré, to mention a few) to take a pluralist approach to the puzzle: why not accept the idea that there are many ways to think about species, and that different biological problems may require the adoption of distinct species concepts?

There is another, though not necessarily incompatible, solution, which makes use of the work of philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein. In his Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein proposed the idea of cluster, or ‘family resemblance’, concepts: some terms by their nature do not admit of an essentialist definition, but are rather characterized by a diffuse network of more or less loosely interconnected properties. Any particular instantiation of the concept may draw on a subset of such threads, even though there is a limit to such conceptual ‘plasticity.’

Wittgenstein’s famous example is the idea of a game: the more one thinks about it, the more it is clear that it is difficult to list a set of characteristics that are necessary and sufficient to define what we mean by ‘game.’ Board games like chess or monopoly clearly have more features in common than any of them has with ball games like soccer or basketball, and yet we meaningfully refer to all of these activities as ‘games.’

To put it as the master did: “How should we explain to someone what a game is? I imagine we should describe games to him, and we might add: ‘This and similar things are called games’” (P.I., para. 69). … “But this is not ignorance. We do not know the boundaries because none have been drawn … We can draw a boundary for a special purpose.” (ibid)

The same holds for species. Not only special purposes (like the very different works of a paleontologist and a geneticist), but also different classes of living organisms (a bacterium vs. a reptile) may require us to think of species as concepts made of a loose cluster of characteristics, some of which turn out to be particularly useful – while some do not apply – in any given circumstance.

As biologist Alan Templeton famously put it, if one insists on using a single (essentialist) criterion to define species, such as interbreeding in the case of the Dobzhansky-Mayr proposal, “the problem, as it is often the case, is sex: either too much or not enough,” meaning whatever unique criterion one chooses ends up been too tight or too loose for a vast class of biological organisms.

Of course, a Wittgensteinian dissolution of the species concept is unlikely to provide practicing biologists with answers to specific empirical questions (“does this individual belong to species X or Y?”). Then again, philosophy was always meant to clarify conceptual issues, not to solve empirical problems. For the latter, science usually suffices.

(header image: the first evolutionary tree of life drawn by Charles Darwin)

Race is a Social Construct

 

4 thoughts on “Wittgenstein Posthumously Solves the Species Problem

  1. I love it when people posthumously solve things! Especially Wittgenstein (of whom, if we wanted to play games, we could say he posthumously solved his own conundrums from the Tractatus after a symbolic death and rebirth in the Great North Woods or wherever the hell he went).

    Liked by 2 people

  2. An inconvenient but interesting alternative is a story, a guess at what caused the changes one sees between similar biota, with as much detail as possible. Where did wolves evolve into dogs. What kind of humans affected the changes? How long did it take? And how many times did this happen with what different kinds of dogs resulting?

    Liked by 2 people

  3. Those are excellent questions to illustrate what we mean when we say a species is much more fuzzy than concrete.

    We can go way back before Darwin and get into Aristotle and teleological explanations.

    Thing is, dogs as we know them today – I have German Shepherds – didn’t exist until recently, when humans figured out how artificial selection works.

    So we know some of the answers to dog questions with a good degree of certainty, which in turn helps us understand how the natural selection Darwin discovered back in the day works.

    https://aeon.co/ideas/dog-breeds-are-mere-victorian-confections-neither-pure-nor-ancient

    Liked by 1 person

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google photo

You are commenting using your Google account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s